- Other
articles
- CLV
Perspective
- CLV
Philosophy
" Someone
who would never even contemplate going to an art gallery or a concert
might, nevertheless be deeply concerned about the things that artists
and those who are interested in art would regard as being of fundamental
importance. It
would, indeed, be very odd if this were not the case..
|
Nature:
Aesthetics/Philosophy/General Education
CLV
rating: AAA
The
central concern of aesthetics is with the nature of our outstanding and
appreciation of art. Some of the questions which it raises are :
Many
people believe that art is a minority interest and that is has little
or no relevance to everyday life. Art, they suppose, is what hangs in
galleries, is displayed in museums, performed in concert halls and theatres,
and discussed in the literature departments if universities, places where
the mass of people are not to be found and probably would not want to
be found.
One
of the most important of all the tasks of aesthetics is to show why it
is wrong to separate art from life in this way. It is also one of the
most difficult.
The
following remakes on the matter are, therefore, no more than suggestions
which seems to me to be worth thinking about.
In
the everyday world most people frequently make judgments of aesthetic
taste. They do so when they chose what to wear, when they purchase jewellery
and kitchen utensils, furnish rooms, use make-up, take photographs, look
at their own bodies in mirrors and other people's bodies on the beach,
walk in the countryside, gaze at the night sky, buy presents, discuses
the environment, wonder where they should live and whom they should marry.
Consider
someone who is trying to decide which dress to wear. She is not just concerned
with covering her body and keeping it warm. She is also concerned with
how the dress looks and feels with its colour and texture and style. She
wonders whether the dress will match other items of clothing, whether
it will go with a particular hair style, skin colour, and type of make-up,
whether it will enhance her appearance or make her look dowdy, whether
it will be suitable for the occasion on which she will wear it, and so
on.
Her
choice is an aesthetic one, an exercise of taste.
It
might be, though, that what is involved in choosing a dress has nothing
in common with Guernica, the B minor Mass and King Lear. But this is not
the case. The aesthetics of everyday life is not different in kind from
the aesthetics of painting, music, architecture and the other arts.
Great
works of art are a product of the imagination and appreciation of them
requires imaginative under-standing. The same type of imaginative activity
takes place when clothes are designed and chosen.
The
person who wonders which dress to wear shares with the artist and the
art-lover a concern for harmony, balance, shape and proportion. She wants
to look exactly right. If she is to achieve this, all the details of her
appearance must be suited to each other and be appearance must be suited
to each other and be appropriate to the context in which the clothes are
to be worn. But this is not essentially different from achievement in
the arts.
A
successful work of art, above everything else, one which provides us with
the sense of being exactly right. We are aware of the interdependence
of all its parts. We feel that there is nothing that could be added to
it or subtracted from it that would improve it.
This
is not the only area in which art and life share common ground. There
is, for instance, a common language.
The
Mona Lisa is beautiful, but so is Mabel Blumenfeld, my pet rabbit, and
moonlight on the Mersey. Fashion models and swans are graceful as well
as Makarova and Baryshnikov.
We
say of both works of art and people that they are sad, cheerful, passionate,
lively, amusing, charming, impulsive, feverish, composed, tranquil, gave,
sober, thrilling, disturbing, and so on. And tragedy and comedy are, of
course, not only to be found in the theatre.
Significantly,
though less obviously, the language of art has much in common with the
language of morals. We admire both works of art and people for their intelligence,
realism, perceptiveness, clarity, sensitivity, emotional depth, spontaneity,
compassion, objectively, wisdom and sincerity.
Art
fails when it is sentimental, insincere, superficial, undiscriminating,
lacking in integrity, and involves wishful thinking and self-deception.
But
these are serious moral faults. The standards by reference to which we
judge works of art are, therefore, the same as those by reference to which
we judge human actions and attitudes and motives.
If
this is true, it raises some interesting questions. For instance can there
be an aesthetically good works of art which is also morally bad? If ethics
and aesthetics share the same standards, the answer would seem to be no.
Even
more interesting : Can someone be a morally good man and have bad aesthetic
taste? Can someone be morally bad and have good aesthetic taste?
Evil
is sometimes said to be banal; that is, it involves an odious lack of
taste, But so do many television programmes. We might wonder, therefore,
how someone can possibly enjoy watching Dallas unless he is morally degenerate.
Is
he different only in degree from someone who enjoys watching people being
tortured? Concentration camp, guards are, after all, notoriously sentimental,
and it is, perhaps, not entirely a coincidence that they have this in
common with the television watcher.
They
both display a lack of realism and perceptiveness about the nature and
quality of their own and other people's experience. In both cases, there
is distortion, muddle, vulgarity and self-indulgence.
If
there is this close connection of what is aesthetic with what is moral,
then a person's aesthetic taste will not be just a part of his life, something
which is essentially unconnected with the rest of it. It will, on the
contrary, express the kind of person that he is.
He
will display in his aesthetic choices and preferences the nature of his
character and fundamental attitudes, the quality of his emotions and intellect,
his political and religious beliefs, his understanding of himself and
others.
And
this will be true not merely of his preferences in the higher forms of
art, but also of the aesthetics of his everyday life; for instance, of
his choice of clothes, furniture, presents, apartment and friends.
A
Sherlock Holmes of aesthetic could, perhaps, detect whether someone was
morally corrupt not by inspecting his bank balance, but by observing his
furnishings and examining his wardrobe.
The
belief that art is not relevant to the everyday lives of most people seems,
therefore, not to be true. People's choices and preferences often involve
aesthetic considerations and their aesthetic taste expresses what is most
central to their identities.
Someone
who would never even contemplate going to an art gallery or a concert
might, nevertheless be deeply concerned about the things that artists
and those who are interested in art would regard as being of fundamental
importance.
It
would, indeed, be very odd if this were not the case. A life from which
the aesthetic sense was completely absent would be one deprived of almost
all of that which makes life interesting and pleasurable.
There
would be no adventures of imagination, no enjoyment of nature, no appreciation
of design or buildings or music, no awareness of beauty, no love.
It
is hard to imagine what a life like that would be like. But whatever it
is like, it is not a life that I, for one, would want to live.
|